LOGIN TO YOUR ACCOUNT

Username
Password
Remember Me
Or use your Academic/Social account:

CREATE AN ACCOUNT

Or use your Academic/Social account:

Congratulations!

You have just completed your registration at OpenAire.

Before you can login to the site, you will need to activate your account. An e-mail will be sent to you with the proper instructions.

Important!

Please note that this site is currently undergoing Beta testing.
Any new content you create is not guaranteed to be present to the final version of the site upon release.

Thank you for your patience,
OpenAire Dev Team.

Close This Message

CREATE AN ACCOUNT

Name:
Username:
Password:
Verify Password:
E-mail:
Verify E-mail:
*All Fields Are Required.
Please Verify You Are Human:
fbtwitterlinkedinvimeoflicker grey 14rssslideshare1
Chambers, Simone (2009)
Publisher: Co-Action Publishing
Journal: Ethics & Global Politics
Languages: English
Types: Article
Subjects: public reason; pluralism; Hobbes; Locke; Kant
This paper investigates early modern and enlightenment roots of contemporary ideas of public reason. I argue that concepts of public reason arose in answer to the question ‘who shall judge?’ The religious and moral pluralism unleashed by the reformation lead first to the weakening of authoritative common forms of reasoning, this in turn and more importantly lead to the question who is the final arbiter when a political community is faced with deep disagreement about political/ moral questions. The rise of pluralism meant that to the question ‘what are the standards of public right?’ is added the corollary and equally important question ‘who judges when those standards are violated?’ The answer is that the public judges. Public reason thus refers to the role of the public as judge of public right and not simply to a set of reasons that an actual public happens to share. On this reading of Hobbes, Locke, and Kant, the initial contract recedes in importance while the seat of authoritative political judgment comes to the fore. Keywords: public reason; pluralism; Hobbes; Locke; Kant (Published: 4 December 2009) Citation: Ethics & Global Politics, Vol. 2, No. 4, 2009, pp. 349368. DOI: 10.3402/egp.v2i4.2135
  • The results below are discovered through our pilot algorithms. Let us know how we are doing!

    • Gerard J. Postema, 'Public Practical Reason: Political Practice', in Nomos XXXVII: Theory and Practice, ed. Ian Shapiro and Judith Wagner DeCew (New York: New York University Press, 1995), 345 85; Duncan Ivison, 'The Secret History of Public Reason: Hobbes to Rawls', History of Political Thought 18, no. 1 (1997), 126 47; Stephan Macedo, Liberal Virtues: Citizenship, Virtue, and Community in Liberal Constitutionalism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990); Jeremy Waldron, 'Theoretical Foundations of Liberalism', in Liberal Rights: Collected Papers 1981 1991, ed. Jeremy Waldron (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), 35 63.
    • It would not be possible to list all the work being done in this area at the moment. The theorists who offer the two most influential paradigms are of course John Rawls and Ju¨ rgen Habermas, but there are a number of other models as well. I offer a brief list of some main contributors: Gerard J. Postema, 'Public Practical Reason: An Archeology', Social Philosophy and Policy 12 (1995), 43 86; David Gauthier, 'Public Reason', Social Philosophy and Policy 12, no. 1 (1995), 19 42; John Rawls, Political Liberalism, paperback ed. (New York: Colombia University Press, 1996); Ju¨ rgen Habermas, 'Reconciliation through the Public Use of Reason', Journal of Philosophy 92, no. 3 (1995), 109 131; Charles Larmore, 'The Moral Basis of Political Liberalism', Journal of Philosophy 96, no. 12 (1999), 599 625; Gerald F. Gaus, Justificatory Liberalism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996).
    • Mark Button also argues that reading Hobbes and Locke as theorists of public reason rather than contract is very rewarding. Button, however, sees the core of their views to be articulated in a theory of transformative education in which public reason is inculcated in citizens. I do not share this view. Mark E. Button, Contract, Culture, and Citizenship: Transformative Liberalism from Hobbes to Rawls (University Park, PA: Pennsylvania State Press, 2008).
    • Rawls, Political Liberalism, 213.
    • Ivison, 'The Secret History of Public Reason: Hobbes to Rawls'; Philip Pettit, Made with Words: Hobbes on Language, Mind, and Politics (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2008).
    • John Gray, 'Pluralism and Toleration in Contemporary Political Philosophy', Political Studies 48, no. 10 (2000), 323 33; Peter Jones, 'Toleration, Value Pluralism, and the Fact of Pluralism', Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 9, no. 2 (2006), 189 210. Value-pluralism is an ethical and sometimes meta-ethical doctrine that maintains that values are irreducibly plural whether or not they are recognized as such by people in general. Value-pluralism is saying something about 'the moral universe we inhabit' and not something in the first instance about the social and political world we inhabit. William A.
    • Galston, Liberal Pluralism: The Implications of Value Pluralism for Political Theory and Practice (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002), 48.
    • William E. Connolly, Pluralism (Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 2005).
    • Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), 128.
    • Ibid., 145.
    • Ibid., 124.
    • Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, trans. Norman Kemp Smith (New York: St. Martin's Press, 1965), A739/B767.
    • Immanuel Kant, 'Practical Philosophy', in Critique of Practical Reason, ed. Mary J. Gregor, vol. 6 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), 237.
    • That human beings live on a globe and so in a limited space is, according to Arthur Ripstein, an essential postulate of the theory. In other words, if we lived in an unlimited space then the solution to the puzzle would be to just move further away from each other. For an excellent and thorough discussion of Kant's political philosophy, see Arthur Ripstein, Force and Freedom: Kant's Legal and Political Philosophy (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2009).
    • Kant, Practical Philosophy, vol. 8, 297.
    • Onora O'Neill, 'The Public Use of Reason', Political Theory 14, no. 4 (1986), 523 51.
    • Kant, Practical Philosophy, vol. 8, 37.
    • For an excellent discussion of this topic, see Elisabeth Ellis, Kant's Politics. Provisional Theory for an Uncertain World (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 2005), and Flikschuh, 'Reason, Right, and Revolution'.
    • Kant, Practical Philosophy, vol. 8, 304.
    • There is a huge literature on this subject in Kant scholarship. For a review of the literature and a defense of Kant's total ban on revolution, see Flikschuh, 'Reason, Right, and Revolution'. See also Ripstein, Force and Freedom, 325 43.
    • Onora O'Neill, Constructions of Reason: Explorations of Kant's Practical Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989).
    • Ellis, Kant's Politics, 37.
    • Locke, Two Treatises, 102.
    • Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, A739/B767.
    • O'Neill 'The Public Use of Reason', 546.
  • No related research data.
  • No similar publications.

Share - Bookmark

Cite this article

Collected from